We’ve just seen experimental evidence that
Let’s write that out.
Rearranging this gives us the following.
This says the ratio of
Video: [youtube]
Slides: [pdf]
Asymptotic Equivalence
Some examples of asymptotic equivalence will help clarify its meaning.If and , then . Both and have the same dominant term .
Swapping and doesn't break asymptotic equivalence, .
However, if and , then and are not asymptotically equivalent because the ratio tends to , not 1.
If we know that and , then we can also say . This property, called transitivity, is familiar from normal equality.
What About li(n)?
Gauss' second approximation appeared to be a better approximation for . You'll find the prime number theorem is sometimes expressed using the logarithmic integral.
Surely the prime number theorem must be about one of the approximations, not both? The only solution is for both approximations to be asymptotically equivalent. Let's see that this is indeed the case.
Let's set and .
To show we need to find the limit of as and confirm it is 1. Sadly, both and become infinitely large as , so the ratio is undefined.
When this happens, we usually try l'Hopital's rule as an alternative way to find the limit.
It's fairly easy to work out , and pops out of the definition of .
So the prime number theorem can refer to either of the two approximations, and , because they are asymptotically equivalent.
What Does The Prime Number Theorem Really Say?
The prime number theorem says that grows in a way that is asymptotically equivalent to functions like and .
It doesn't say that these are the only or best functions for approximating , which leaves open the intriguing possibility of other functions that are even better than .
Bertrand's Postulate
The prime number theorem, even if it looks imprecise, is rather useful. Let's look at a particularly simple example.
In 1845 Bertrand proposed that there is at least one prime between a counting number and its double, .
Let's compare the number of primes up to , with the number of primes up to .
This shows that for sufficiently large , between and , there are primes. This is a stronger statement than Bertrand's postulate which merely suggests there is at least one prime.
There are proofs that don't require to be sufficiently large, but they're nowhere near as simple as this deduction from the prime number theorem.
No comments:
Post a Comment